CZ:Featured article/Current: Difference between revisions

From Citizendium
Jump to navigation Jump to search
imported>John Stephenson
m (typo)
imported>Chunbum Park
mNo edit summary
Line 21: Line 21:


[[Vesalius|Andreas Vesalius’s]]  biographer, C. D. O’Malley, credits Alcmaeon as the earliest known “genuine student of anatomy”:
[[Vesalius|Andreas Vesalius’s]]  biographer, C. D. O’Malley, credits Alcmaeon as the earliest known “genuine student of anatomy”:
<blockquote>
<blockquote><p style="font-size: 1.0em; font-family: Gill Sans MT, Trebuchet MS;">The earliest known genuine student of anatomy appears to have been Alcmaeon  of Crotona, who lived in southern Italy, c. 500 B.C. Only the slightest fragments of his writing remain, but from these it does appear that he was the first to make dissections of animals, probably goats, and although almost nothing is known of the results, he did make the very important declaration that the brain is the central organ  of intelligence.<ref name=omalley1964>O'Malley CD. (1964) Andreas Vesalius of Brussels, 1514-1564. Berkeley: University of California Press.
 
*<u>Note:</u>&nbsp;<font face="Gill Sans MT">Considered the definitive biography. Renown historian of medicine, F. N. L. Poynter, stated of Dr. O'Malley's book: "What strikes me immediately on reading Professor O'Malley's monumental work is the coolness of its judgment, the absence of any kind of special pleading or even of that warmth of expression which comes from the biographer's identification with his subject. This almost Olympian detachment is rare indeed and not to be found in any of the outstanding examples of the biographer's art which readily spring to mind." (See F. N. L. POYNTER. 1964. [http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/jhmas/XIX.4.321 Andreas Vesalius of Brussels — 1514-1564: A Brief Survey of Recent Work.] Journal of the History of Medicine and Allied Sciences 1964 XIX(4):321-326. PMID 14215447</font></ref></p></blockquote>
<p style="margin-left: 2.0%; margin-right: 6%; font-size: 1.0em; font-family: Gill Sans MT, Trebuchet MS;">The earliest known genuine student of anatomy appears to have been Alcmaeon  of Crotona, who lived in southern Italy, c. 500 B.C. Only the slightest fragments of his writing remain, but from these it does appear that he was the first to make dissections of animals, probably goats, and although almost nothing is known of the results, he did make the very important declaration that the brain is the central organ  of intelligence.<ref name=omalley1964>O'Malley CD. (1964) Andreas Vesalius of Brussels, 1514-1564. Berkeley: University of California Press.
*<u>Note:</u>&nbsp;<font face="Gill Sans MT">Considered the definitive biography. Renown historian of medicine, F. N. L. Poynter, stated of Dr. O'Malley's book: "What strikes me immediately on reading Professor O'Malley's monumental work is the coolness of its judgment, the absence of any kind of special pleading or even of that warmth of expression which comes from the biographer's identification with his subject. This almost Olympian detachment is rare indeed and not to be found in any of the outstanding examples of the biographer's art which readily spring to mind." (See F. N. L. POYNTER. 1964. [http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/jhmas/XIX.4.321 Andreas Vesalius of Brussels — 1514-1564: A Brief Survey of Recent Work.] Journal of the History of Medicine and Allied Sciences 1964 XIX(4):321-326. PMID 14215447</font></ref></p>
 
</blockquote>


J. B. Wilbur and H. J. Allen give this introduction to Alcmaeon:
J. B. Wilbur and H. J. Allen give this introduction to Alcmaeon:
<blockquote>
<blockquote><p style="font-size: 1.0em; font-family: Gill Sans MT, Trebuchet MS;">Physiology and medicine were Alcmaeon's prime interest, which accounts for his concern with cognition and the nature of the soul. Because medicine had not yet emerged as a distinct discipline, however, Alcmaeon also expressed opinions on the immortality of the soul as well as on astronomy and cosmology--thus going beyond the limitations of his own medical empiricism. There are no fragments and little other information concerning his views on these last two subjects, but in any case it would seem that Alcmaeon's contributions are his ideas concerning knowledge and the soul.<ref name=wilburallen>Wilbur JB, Allen HJ. (1979) [http://www.questia.com/read/82239065 The Worlds of the Early Greek Philosophers.] Prometheus Books: Buffalo, NY.
<p style="margin-left: 2.0%; margin-right: 6%; font-size: 1.0em; font-family: Gill Sans MT, Trebuchet MS;">Physiology and medicine were Alcmaeon's prime interest, which accounts for his concern with cognition and the nature of the soul. Because medicine had not yet emerged as a distinct discipline, however, Alcmaeon also expressed opinions on the immortality of the soul as well as on astronomy and cosmology--thus going beyond the limitations of his own medical empiricism. There are no fragments and little other information concerning his views on these last two subjects, but in any case it would seem that Alcmaeon's contributions are his ideas concerning knowledge and the soul.<ref name=wilburallen>Wilbur JB, Allen HJ. (1979) [http://www.questia.com/read/82239065 The Worlds of the Early Greek Philosophers.] Prometheus Books: Buffalo, NY.
*<u>About this book, from its Preface:</u>&nbsp;<font face="Gill Sans MT">The authors of this book have tried to do two things in presenting the written materials ascribed to the early Greek philosophers (c. 585 B.C.-400 B.C.) and the historical context in which those writings occurred. The first was to present a more fully fleshed out picture of the ideas of these men than has been given in the past. Perhaps under the influence of a narrow empiricism there has been a preference for letting the fragments speak for themselves. The trouble with this approach is that, even where there is a goodly number of fragments left, as, for instance, by Heraclitus, an adequate context for interpretation is not always evident from the fragments alone. And in the case of a thinker such as Anaximander, on the other hand, where there is so little firsthand evidence, what does remain is obscure taken solely on its own terms. Opposed to this Scylla of parsimony, there is, of course, the Charybdis of prodigal speculation. But we did not wish to hew a predetermined course equidistant from these two extremes. Rather the goal was to suit our passage to the winds and waters, sometimes nearer one than the other, as seemed best....The second aim, also in the nature of a mean between extremes, was to find a happy balance between overwhelming the reader with all the scholarly paraphernalia of etymology and philology, and presenting a stripped-down version of the ideas that conveys no sense of the condition and source of our knowledge about them. While, for all but the specialist, the former detracts from the ideas presented, the latter fails to give a proper appreciation of the subject. In practice, this means that we<tried to indicate, whenever possible, who attributed an idea to a given philosopher while at the same time providing the student with the relevant passage so he can read for himself what, for instance, Heraclitus said about Pythagoras. For this reason, the fragments themselves as well as essential interpretive passages are included in the text. Testimonials by other thinkers, which are of great importance to our knowledge of the earliest of these Greek philosophers, are either included in the body of the text or referred to at the bottom of the page, depending upon their relevance. A guide to these testimonial sources appears at the end of the book, along with a selected bibliography for the period as well as for the thinkers.</font></ref></p></blockquote>
*<u>About this book, from its Preface:</u>&nbsp;<font face="Gill Sans MT">The authors of this book have tried to do two things in presenting the written materials ascribed to the early Greek philosophers (c. 585 B.C.-400 B.C.) and the historical context in which those writings occurred. The first was to present a more fully fleshed out picture of the ideas of these men than has been given in the past. Perhaps under the influence of a narrow empiricism there has been a preference for letting the fragments speak for themselves. The trouble with this approach is that, even where there is a goodly number of fragments left, as, for instance, by Heraclitus, an adequate context for interpretation is not always evident from the fragments alone. And in the case of a thinker such as Anaximander, on the other hand, where there is so little firsthand evidence, what does remain is obscure taken solely on its own terms. Opposed to this Scylla of parsimony, there is, of course, the Charybdis of prodigal speculation. But we did not wish to hew a predetermined course equidistant from these two extremes. Rather the goal was to suit our passage to the winds and waters, sometimes nearer one than the other, as seemed best....The second aim, also in the nature of a mean between extremes, was to find a happy balance between overwhelming the reader with all the scholarly paraphernalia of etymology and philology, and presenting a stripped-down version of the ideas that conveys no sense of the condition and source of our knowledge about them. While, for all but the specialist, the former detracts from the ideas presented, the latter fails to give a proper appreciation of the subject. In practice, this means that we<tried to indicate, whenever possible, who attributed an idea to a given philosopher while at the same time providing the student with the relevant passage so he can read for himself what, for instance, Heraclitus said about Pythagoras. For this reason, the fragments themselves as well as essential interpretive passages are included in the text. Testimonials by other thinkers, which are of great importance to our knowledge of the earliest of these Greek philosophers, are either included in the body of the text or referred to at the bottom of the page, depending upon their relevance. A guide to these testimonial sources appears at the end of the book, along with a selected bibliography for the period as well as for the thinkers.</font></ref></p>


</blockquote>
''[[Alcmaeon of Croton|.... (read more)]]''
''[[Alcmaeon of Croton|.... (read more)]]''



Revision as of 08:06, 1 January 2012

Alcmaeon of Croton

by Anthony.Sebastian


Alcmaeon, also Alcmaeon of Croton, was an ancient Greek early-vintage natural philosopher.[1] Alcmaeon had a wide spectrum of interests in natural phenomena (astronomical, anatomical, biological, cognitive, medical, inter alia), offering explanations of them in rational mechanistic terms as opposed to the prevailing explanations in terms of supernatural forces, and he had a particular interest in medicine and physiology.[2]

Longrigg states that of the medical theories of those natural philosophers in the era before Hippocrates of Kos (who, with his disciples, left an extensive body of writings known as the Hippocratic treatises), only those of Alcmaeon have survived to any significant extent.[3]

Ancient and modern scholars generally hold Alcmaeon in high esteem as an innovative thinker, as the originator or early proponent of the rationalistic explanation of health and disease, as an experimentalist, and as having a major influence on the development of Western medicine, in part through his influence on Hippocrates and his disciples.[3] "[Alcmaeon's] anatomical researches, particularly into the structure of the eye, and his connecting the senses with the brain...mark him as a pioneer in pure medical science."[4] Scholars have credited Alcmaeon as the first person to recognize the brain as the organ of sense perception, of intelligence, and as the seat of the mind.[5] [6]

Alcmaeon was born in about 515 BCE and lived sometime in the 500s BCE in the Greek city of Croton in Italy. Alcmaeon lived during and near the times of Pythagorus (ca. 570 – 490 BCE), also in Croton, and before Hippocrates of Kos (460 – ca. 370 BCE).[7] [3] [2] [8]

Contributions of Alcmaeon

Andreas Vesalius’s biographer, C. D. O’Malley, credits Alcmaeon as the earliest known “genuine student of anatomy”:

The earliest known genuine student of anatomy appears to have been Alcmaeon of Crotona, who lived in southern Italy, c. 500 B.C. Only the slightest fragments of his writing remain, but from these it does appear that he was the first to make dissections of animals, probably goats, and although almost nothing is known of the results, he did make the very important declaration that the brain is the central organ of intelligence.[9]

J. B. Wilbur and H. J. Allen give this introduction to Alcmaeon:

Physiology and medicine were Alcmaeon's prime interest, which accounts for his concern with cognition and the nature of the soul. Because medicine had not yet emerged as a distinct discipline, however, Alcmaeon also expressed opinions on the immortality of the soul as well as on astronomy and cosmology--thus going beyond the limitations of his own medical empiricism. There are no fragments and little other information concerning his views on these last two subjects, but in any case it would seem that Alcmaeon's contributions are his ideas concerning knowledge and the soul.[10]

.... (read more)