Physical determinism

From Citizendium
Revision as of 12:39, 27 January 2013 by imported>John R. Brews (→‎References)
Jump to navigation Jump to search
This article is developing and not approved.
Main Article
Discussion
Related Articles  [?]
Bibliography  [?]
External Links  [?]
Citable Version  [?]
 
This editable Main Article is under development and subject to a disclaimer.

Physical determinism is a position in philosophy that holds that a complete description of the physical state of the world at any given time and a complete statement of the physical laws of nature together entail every truth as to what physical events happen after that time.[1] In different words, physical determinism holds that all physical events occur as described by physical laws.[2]

Sometimes the restrictions to physical events and physical laws are ignored, and physical determinism is used as a synonym for nomological determinism, that all future events are determined by the past or present. However, in this article this practice is avoided.

The initial definition leaves open just what "physical" might mean, or a "complete" description. So, for example, one could limit the scope of physical determinism as

"a concept only relevant to the mathematical models of physics and other physical sciences, although its relevance to the world of everyday choice and action is questionable...if thoughts, feelings, and desires are not physical events, it is unlikely that physical theories are appropriate models for thinking about such nonphysical events."[2] —Robert C. Bishop Chaos, indeterminism, and free will, p. 84

Causal completeness

The scope of physical determinism is related to the question of the causal completeness of science, the idea that every real event has a scientific explanation, that science need not search for explanations beyond itself.[3]. If causal completeness does not apply to everything in the universe, then the door is open to events that are not subject to physical determinism.[4] For example, a common view of mental events is that they are an epiphenomenon only correlated with neurological activity, and without causal impact. However, a failure of physical determinism would allow room for their causal significance.

A more general formulation of physical determinism skirts the issue of causal completeness. It is based upon connections between 'events' supplied by a theory:

"a theory is deterministic if, and only if, given its state variables for some initial period, the theory logically determines a unique set of values for those variables for any other period."[5] —Ernest Nagel Alternative descriptions of physical state, p. 292

This quote replaces the idea of 'cause-and-effect' with that of 'logical implication' according to one or another theory that connects events.[6] In addition, an 'event' is related by the theory itself to formalized states described using the parameters defined by that theory. Thus, the details of interpretation are placed where they belong, fitted to the context in which the chosen theory applies. Using the definition of physical determinism above, the limitations of a theory to some particular domain of experience also limits the associated definition of 'physical determinism' to that same domain. That limitation leaves open the question whether there is a physical "theory of everything" still to be invented.

Popper's three worlds

A much more general reservation about the applicability of physical determinism stems from the formulation of Popper's three worlds. Popper split the world into three categories:[7]

  • World 1: the world of physical objects and events, including biological entities
  • World 2: the mental or psychological world, the world of our feelings of pain and of pleasure, of our thoughts, of our decisions, of our perceptions and our observations; in other words, the world of mental or psychological states or processes, or of subjective experiences.
  • World 3: the world of products of the human mind, including art, science, and religion.

World 3 includes physical theory as a particular case. But World 3 is a creation of the human imagination, and such acts of imagination are a part of World 2. Accordingly, one could argue that physical determinism is a child of the imagination, and although physical determinism has its successes in describing World 1, it may not apply to World 2 or World 3. The subjective aspects of theories contained in World 3 are not readily framed within the third-person perspective of science used to explain World 1. These subjective aspects are described in the article Subjective-objective dichotomy.

References

  1. This definition is from Carl Ginet (1990). On Action. Cambridge University Press, p. 92. ISBN 052138818X. 
  2. 2.0 2.1 Robert C Bishop (2011). “Chapter 4: Chaos, indeterminism, and free will”, Robert Kane, ed: The Oxford Handbook of Free Will: Second Edition, 2nd. Oxford University Press, p. 84. ISBN 0195399692. 
  3. See for example, Sahotra Sarkar, Jessica Pfeifer (2006). “Physicalism: The causal impact argument”, The Philosophy of Science: N-Z, Index. Taylor & Francis, p. 566. ISBN 041597710X. 
  4. Robert C Bishop, Harald Atmanspacher (2011). “Chapter 5: The causal closure of physics and free will”, Robert Kane, ed: The Oxford Handbook of Free Will: Second Edition, 2nd. Oxford University Press, p. 101. ISBN 0195399692. 
  5. Ernest Nagel (1999). “§V: Alternative descriptions of physical state”, The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation, 2nd. Hackett, pp. 285-292. ISBN 0915144719. 
  6. The notion of cause introduces unnecessary complications best avoided as done here. For example, see Bertrand Russell (1912-1913). "On the notion of cause". Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (New Series) 13: pp. 1-26.
  7. Karl Popper (April 7, 1978). Three Worlds. The Tanner lectures on human values. The University of Utah. Retrieved on 2013-01-24. The list of lectures is found in the Tanner Lecture Library.