Cogito ergo sum: Difference between revisions

From Citizendium
Jump to navigation Jump to search
imported>Larry Sanger
(Adding info about the statement and its location)
imported>Larry Sanger
(working...)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{subpages}}
{{subpages}}


'''"Cogito ergo sum,"''' Latin for "I think, therefore I am," is [[Descartes]]' most famous catchphrase and one of the most famous sentences of [[philosophy]].  This idea is often thought to be a turning point in the [[history of philosophy]], making the certainty of individual [[consciousness]] its new starting point.
'''"Cogito ergo sum,"''' Latin for "I think, therefore I am," is [[Rene Descartes]]' most famous catchphrase and one of the most famous sentences of [[philosophy]].  This idea is often thought to be a turning point in the [[history of philosophy]], making the certainty of individual [[consciousness]] the new foundation of knowledge.


The ''cogito,'' as the statement is often called, occurs most famously in the ''[[Discourse on Method]],'' Part 4, but not, as is sometimes, in the main text of the ''[[Meditations on First Philosophy]].''<ref>Though it does appear in one of the replies (need exact reference).</ref> One might think it occurs in Meditation Two, since this is where he develops the argument described in the rest of this article, but it does not; it appears in ''Discourse'' Part 4, which is a summary of the argument of the ''[[Meditations on First Philosophy]].''
The ''cogito,'' as the statement is often called, occurs most famously in the ''[[Discourse on Method]],'' Part 4, but not, as is sometimes thought, in the main text of the ''[[Meditations on First Philosophy]].''<ref>Though it does appear in one of the Objections and Replies (need exact reference).  One might think it occurs in Meditation Two, since this is where he develops the argument described in the rest of this article, but it does not.</ref>


The ''cogito'' is sometimes but not always considered to be an [[argument]].   
The ''cogito'' is sometimes but not always considered to be an [[argument]].   

Revision as of 19:17, 18 January 2008

This article is developing and not approved.
Main Article
Discussion
Related Articles  [?]
Bibliography  [?]
External Links  [?]
Citable Version  [?]
 
This editable Main Article is under development and subject to a disclaimer.

"Cogito ergo sum," Latin for "I think, therefore I am," is Rene Descartes' most famous catchphrase and one of the most famous sentences of philosophy. This idea is often thought to be a turning point in the history of philosophy, making the certainty of individual consciousness the new foundation of knowledge.

The cogito, as the statement is often called, occurs most famously in the Discourse on Method, Part 4, but not, as is sometimes thought, in the main text of the Meditations on First Philosophy.[1]

The cogito is sometimes but not always considered to be an argument.

The steps of the argument are quite simple. Descartes first claims that so many former truths have been shown not to stand up to scrutiny, that philosophy needs a new starting point. In his search for this new fulcrum he adopts two methodological devices: not to examine individual claims to knowledge, but rather their basis (sense perception or reason, for example), and to discard as false any statement that isn't evidently true. The latter device allows him to discard anything of which he might have the slightest cause for doubt.

The first victim of his analysis is knowledge based on sense perception. We are often deceived by our senses, so clearly they cannot provide us with the sort of foundational truth we need. Even those sensations that seem so direct and unquestionable to our senses that they couldn't be false, can be questioned when we realize that we often dream that we are feeling them, only to discover later that it wasn't the case. If we cannot distinguish being awake from sleeping, then sense perception can never lead to certain knowledge.

The truths of mathematics would seem a more probable case for certain truths, especially for a mathematician like Descartes, but he introduces the possibility that these truths could have been introduced into our minds by God who wished to deceive us by making us think they are true. He soon backs away from this idea, claiming God could not possibly wish this evil on us, and changes him for an evil demon powerful enough to achieve the same result. Given this new hypothesis not even the truths of mathematics can be saved.

At this point Descartes realizes that while he can subject everything to doubt, the only thing that he cannot dismiss is the very fact that he is doubting. No form of thought can be skeptical of its own existence without serious contradiction, so thinking in its various mental guises, is something of which he can be completely certain. Thinking is proof of my existence!

  1. Though it does appear in one of the Objections and Replies (need exact reference). One might think it occurs in Meditation Two, since this is where he develops the argument described in the rest of this article, but it does not.