Cosmology: Difference between revisions
imported>Thomas Simmons |
imported>Thomas Simmons |
||
Line 22: | Line 22: | ||
A number of things had to develop if there was to be a significant change in cosmology: the development of science; the attitude that would compel people to challenge the status quo; the means to make more precise observations and reveal the vast extent of the universe; and the means to measure and calculate data to arrive at rational, mathematically derived models. Eventually astronomers took issue with the problems Ptolemy's model presented when compared with the data they gathered. | A number of things had to develop if there was to be a significant change in cosmology: the development of science; the attitude that would compel people to challenge the status quo; the means to make more precise observations and reveal the vast extent of the universe; and the means to measure and calculate data to arrive at rational, mathematically derived models. Eventually astronomers took issue with the problems Ptolemy's model presented when compared with the data they gathered. | ||
===William Gilbert=== | |||
One of the first, if not ''the'' first scientist, was a man named '''William Gilbert''' (1544-1603). Gilbert's world was infused with the mystical and the world had been seen through mystical perspectives long before Aristotle posited a "Prime Mover" to explain how the world was set in motion. Gilbert had the attitude, the drive to simply say, "Is that true?" and then test the idea to reveal its credibility. Galileo credited Gilbert as the first true scientist.<ref>[http://www.astro.cornell.edu/academics/courses/astro201/aristotle.htm Aristotle (384 - 322 B.C.)] History of Astronomy, Astronomy, Cornell University</ref><ref>Smoot, George, Davidson, Keay (1993). Wrinkles in time: The imprint of creation. London: Abacus Books</ref><ref>Gribbin, J. (2002) Science: A history. London: Penguin</ref> | One of the first, if not ''the'' first scientist, was a man named '''William Gilbert''' (1544-1603). Gilbert's world was infused with the mystical and the world had been seen through mystical perspectives long before Aristotle posited a "Prime Mover" to explain how the world was set in motion. Gilbert had the attitude, the drive to simply say, "Is that true?" and then test the idea to reveal its credibility. Galileo credited Gilbert as the first true scientist.<ref>[http://www.astro.cornell.edu/academics/courses/astro201/aristotle.htm Aristotle (384 - 322 B.C.)] History of Astronomy, Astronomy, Cornell University</ref><ref>Smoot, George, Davidson, Keay (1993). Wrinkles in time: The imprint of creation. London: Abacus Books</ref><ref>Gribbin, J. (2002) Science: A history. London: Penguin</ref> | ||
===Georg Peurbach=== | |||
'''Georg Peurbach''' (1423-1461) addressed errors in astronomy texts that predated Ptolemy and wrote a new textbook and guide to Ptolemy’s ''Almagest''. Peurbach's ''New Theory of the Planets'' (published 1454) addressed problems encountered in earlier models employing descriptive geometrics to predict planetary motions. | '''Georg Peurbach''' (1423-1461) addressed errors in astronomy texts that predated Ptolemy and wrote a new textbook and guide to Ptolemy’s ''Almagest''. Peurbach's ''New Theory of the Planets'' (published 1454) addressed problems encountered in earlier models employing descriptive geometrics to predict planetary motions. | ||
===Johannes Regiomontanus=== | |||
'''Johannes Regiomontanus''' (1436-1476), a student of Georg Peurbach, continued his work of observation and critique, improving translations of the ancient Greek works, and openly pointing out the discrepancies between observations and current astronomical theory. | '''Johannes Regiomontanus''' (1436-1476), a student of Georg Peurbach, continued his work of observation and critique, improving translations of the ancient Greek works, and openly pointing out the discrepancies between observations and current astronomical theory. | ||
===Nicolaus Copernicus=== | |||
[[Nicolaus Copernicus]] (Nikolas Kopernig, 1473-1543) established, at long last, the heliocentric theory putting the solar system in orbit around the sun and thereby resolving many of the problems that Ptolemy and others had striven to answer with increasingly complicated models of the universe. | [[Nicolaus Copernicus]] (Nikolas Kopernig, 1473-1543) established, at long last, the heliocentric theory putting the solar system in orbit around the sun and thereby resolving many of the problems that Ptolemy and others had striven to answer with increasingly complicated models of the universe. | ||
===Leonard Digges=== | |||
'''Leonard Digges''' (1520-1559) invented the theodolite, the telescope, the reflecting telescope and possibly the refractive telescope providing cosmology with the means to an end--practical and precise observations to serve the theoretical. | '''Leonard Digges''' (1520-1559) invented the theodolite, the telescope, the reflecting telescope and possibly the refractive telescope providing cosmology with the means to an end--practical and precise observations to serve the theoretical. | ||
===Thomas Digges=== | |||
'''Thomas Digges''' (1543-1595), son of Leonard, continued his work, attempted to resolve questions with observations with the telescope and posited the infinite universe. | '''Thomas Digges''' (1543-1595), son of Leonard, continued his work, attempted to resolve questions with observations with the telescope and posited the infinite universe. | ||
===Galileo Galilei=== | |||
[[Galileo Galilei]] (1564-1642) supported the heliocentric model, employed practical observations with telescopes of his own construction, made precise measurements and first introduced concepts of inertia and relativity of motion. | [[Galileo Galilei]] (1564-1642) supported the heliocentric model, employed practical observations with telescopes of his own construction, made precise measurements and first introduced concepts of inertia and relativity of motion. | ||
[[Johannes Kepler]] (1571 - 1630) was instrumental in marrying the best observational data of the time (that of [[Tycho Brahe]]) and the most plausible cosmological model of the time (that of Copernicus). Kepler abandoned the Aristotelian perfection of circular orbits and posited the elliptical, and resolved the problems of period and area of orbits. | ===Johannes Kepler=== | ||
[[Johannes Kepler]] (1571-1630) was instrumental in marrying the best observational data of the time (that of [[Tycho Brahe]]) and the most plausible cosmological model of the time (that of Copernicus). Kepler abandoned the Aristotelian perfection of circular orbits and posited the elliptical, and resolved the problems of period and area of orbits. | |||
===Robert Hooke=== | |||
'''Robert Hooke''' (1635-1703) posited some major theories and invented or improved practical apparatus that would enhance methods of analyses of cosmological phenomena. | |||
He developed more accurate time keeping devices by inventing a spring control for the balance wheel in watches, enhancing the accuracy of measuring movement of celestial bodies as well as improving navigation. He was possibly the first to stress the need for resolving power and point out the advantages of using hair lines in place of silk or metal wire. He built the one of first reflecting telescopes, observed and described the rotation of Mars, was the first to infer the rotation of Jupiter, and described one of the earliest examples of a double star. | |||
Hooke’s wave theory of light was an essential step forward in spectrum analysis.<ref>When Issac Newton produced his theory of light and colur in 1672, Hooke took credit for it claiming that Newton had stolen his ideas about light in 1665. The year following Hooke’s death, Issac Newton published his work on light and colour, ''Opticks'', in which he gave no credit to Hooke. Newton also removed all mention of Hooke from ''Principia''</ref> | |||
Hooke was the first to propose that the motions of astronomical bodies were a matter of dynamics. He published, ''Attempt to Prove the Motion of the Earth'' (1674), in which he offered a theory of planetary motion. employing the correct principle of inertia and a balance between an outward centrifugal force and an inward gravitational attraction to the Sun. He proffered three principles of gravity in a lecture entitled “System of the World,” given in 1674 | |||
*“ . .all Coelestial Bodies whatsoever have an attraction or gravitating power towards their own Centers, whereby they attract not only their own parts, and keep them flying from them . . . but they do also attract all the other Coelestial Bodies that are within the sphere of their activity” | |||
*”. . . all bodies whatsoever that are put into a direct and simple motion, will continue to move forward in a straight line, till they are by some other effectual powers deflected and bent into a Motion describing a Circle, Ellipses, or some other more compounded Curve Line. Hooke predeceased Issac Newton and this was later claimed by Newton. It is now referred to as Newton’s First Law of Motion. | |||
*In that same lecture he also posited the strength of the attraction but wrongly suggested that gravity falls off inversely with distance from the object. He later corrected this in 1679, in a letter to Newton in which he suggested that this attraction would vary inversely as the square of the distance from the Sun. Hooke's theory was qualitatively correct. However he did not have the mathematical skills to provide exact and quantitative definition.<ref>[http://www.roberthooke.org.uk/robert_hooke.htm Robert Hooke]</ref> <ref>[http://www.maths.tcd.ie/pub/HistMath/People/17thCentury/RouseBall/RB_Math17C.html#Hooke Hooke] Wilkins, D.R. School of Math, Trinity College, Dublin</ref><ref>[http://www.ucmp.berkeley.edu/history/hooke.html Robert Hooke (1635-1703)] University of California Museum of Paleontology><ref>[http://www-groups.dcs.st-and.ac.uk:80/~history/Biographies/Hooke.html Robert Hooke] School of Math & Stats. University of St. Andrews</ref> | |||
==Modern Cosmology== | ==Modern Cosmology== |
Revision as of 06:36, 27 December 2007
Cosmology[1]is a branch of astronomy and of metaphysics committed to the study of the universe as a whole, of the contents, structure, and evolution of the universe from the beginning of time to the future.
As a branch of two very old endeavours of humanity, the study of the sky and the origins of the world, it embraces numerous related inquiries concerned with the world we live in and, to the extent it could be imagined and observed, the universe. As a branch of metaphysics it attained some prominence when Christian von Wolffe published Discursus Praeliminaris de Philosophia in Genere (1728). Von Wolff placed cosmology in his classification scheme of the main areas of philosophy, distinguishing cosmology from ontology, theology and psychology, essentially making it a distinctive field of philosophy unto itself. As a philosphy, its nature has been disputed over time since von Wolff but it can be said that generally, it is thought to encompass humanity's experience in, and the nature of, the physical world. As a science, it encompasses the work of observational astronomy and theoretical physics as scholars in both fields attempt to describe and explain the physical universe. Cosmology, as a science, attempts to construct models of the physical universe from observational data which are then tested. Cosmology, as metaphysics, involves a priori investigations of a rational cosmology and the conceptual and categorical analyses of the speculative philosopher.[2]
Ancient cosmology
Any attempt to understand cosmology, or simply what humanity thought about the universe whenever that might have occurred to them prior to the last few millennium would be largely guess work. Their understanding would have been inextricably interwoven with their impressions and their imagination. Impressions would have been made in a facile manner, what ever they could see where ever they were, their immediate circumstance, their fears and attempts at explaining the mysterious, all would have come together in a variety of concepts about the nature of the universe.
What we consider cosmology today, if we are addressing explanations from observations and precise measurements that can be duplicated--the scientific approach--or at least its basic and most primitive roots, it would have been fraught with almost anything but what we consider scientific. Simple deduction about how fire is made and food accessed and shelter constructed would have been within the reach of prehistoric and ancient humanity, but how close they came to an understanding, no matter how fragmented or trivial, of the universe as we know it today, is simply beyond us to ever know. That they observed that things seemed to be regular and predictable is evident from stone circles and other constructions that indicated they knew the sun would strike a certain point on the ground at a certain time every year, the moon would change appearance on a regular basis--any number of possible conclusions could be reached about these clues that have been left. Burial customs going back as far as the last twenty millennium might indicate a belief in the after life, possibly an eternal existence—but that too is reaching and can not be safely concluded.
Since prehistoric people left only fragments of their impressions in relics and documents and instruments of most ancient sources have long since disappeared, prehistoric and ancient humanity's understanding will always be a fragmented picture to us today. In fact, if the definition of cosmology would be constructed around what it was meant to achieve, if it was meant to explain things, it would not necessarily follow that those explanations would be tested as we expect scientific theories to be tested today. The result of such explanations would be extraordinary people, monsters, places and events which would not be verifiable, such as monsters at the edge of the world as mariners sometimes believed as late as the 15th century.
The first solid evidence of a cosmological model that would explain observations come to us from the Greeks of the 4th century B.C.. Babylonians in the 4th millennium B.C. were making accurate observations of the planets, the moon, the stars and the Sun and were providing reasonable predictions of their motions, but they did not leave us with a model to explain these motions as the Greeks did.
The Greeks over time developed a cosmological perspective that the stars were placed firmly and unchangingly in the sky in a sphere that rotated around the Earth every 24 hours. Likewise, the planets, the Sun and the Moon, everything not on the Earth moved in a zone of aether between the Earth and the stars.
This model had many contributors and some detractors, unfortunately the records of their thoughts and work are often fragmentary at best and some we know of only through the comments of others. By the second century, Ptolemy of Alexandria (he may have been Egyptian or he may have been Greek) set down a system to account for the motion of the planets and the Sun and the Moon and the stars around the Earth, a model that was based on perfect circles and epicycles to explain loops observed in planetary motions, loops that were actually retrograde motion caused by the motion of the Earth's movement around the Sun along with the other planets. It was a very complicated system and it stood for a long time. Its demise was posited by quite a number of people over the centuries, even before Ptolemy. but it was not seriously rejected until Galileo.[3][4] Even the concept of aether lasted until the late 19th century when the Michelson-Morley Experiment failed to account for the aether wind.[5]
Medieval cosmology
The Medieval period is generally cast as that time when the Roman Empire withdrew from the West and the coming of the Renaissance, a period of approximately 476 to 1453 A.D. In this period the work of Ptolemy held sway, the universe was geocentric, it moved about the Earth which was the center of the universe.
Renaissance cosmology
A number of things had to develop if there was to be a significant change in cosmology: the development of science; the attitude that would compel people to challenge the status quo; the means to make more precise observations and reveal the vast extent of the universe; and the means to measure and calculate data to arrive at rational, mathematically derived models. Eventually astronomers took issue with the problems Ptolemy's model presented when compared with the data they gathered.
William Gilbert
One of the first, if not the first scientist, was a man named William Gilbert (1544-1603). Gilbert's world was infused with the mystical and the world had been seen through mystical perspectives long before Aristotle posited a "Prime Mover" to explain how the world was set in motion. Gilbert had the attitude, the drive to simply say, "Is that true?" and then test the idea to reveal its credibility. Galileo credited Gilbert as the first true scientist.[6][7][8]
Georg Peurbach
Georg Peurbach (1423-1461) addressed errors in astronomy texts that predated Ptolemy and wrote a new textbook and guide to Ptolemy’s Almagest. Peurbach's New Theory of the Planets (published 1454) addressed problems encountered in earlier models employing descriptive geometrics to predict planetary motions.
Johannes Regiomontanus
Johannes Regiomontanus (1436-1476), a student of Georg Peurbach, continued his work of observation and critique, improving translations of the ancient Greek works, and openly pointing out the discrepancies between observations and current astronomical theory.
Nicolaus Copernicus
Nicolaus Copernicus (Nikolas Kopernig, 1473-1543) established, at long last, the heliocentric theory putting the solar system in orbit around the sun and thereby resolving many of the problems that Ptolemy and others had striven to answer with increasingly complicated models of the universe.
Leonard Digges
Leonard Digges (1520-1559) invented the theodolite, the telescope, the reflecting telescope and possibly the refractive telescope providing cosmology with the means to an end--practical and precise observations to serve the theoretical.
Thomas Digges
Thomas Digges (1543-1595), son of Leonard, continued his work, attempted to resolve questions with observations with the telescope and posited the infinite universe.
Galileo Galilei
Galileo Galilei (1564-1642) supported the heliocentric model, employed practical observations with telescopes of his own construction, made precise measurements and first introduced concepts of inertia and relativity of motion.
Johannes Kepler
Johannes Kepler (1571-1630) was instrumental in marrying the best observational data of the time (that of Tycho Brahe) and the most plausible cosmological model of the time (that of Copernicus). Kepler abandoned the Aristotelian perfection of circular orbits and posited the elliptical, and resolved the problems of period and area of orbits.
Robert Hooke
Robert Hooke (1635-1703) posited some major theories and invented or improved practical apparatus that would enhance methods of analyses of cosmological phenomena.
He developed more accurate time keeping devices by inventing a spring control for the balance wheel in watches, enhancing the accuracy of measuring movement of celestial bodies as well as improving navigation. He was possibly the first to stress the need for resolving power and point out the advantages of using hair lines in place of silk or metal wire. He built the one of first reflecting telescopes, observed and described the rotation of Mars, was the first to infer the rotation of Jupiter, and described one of the earliest examples of a double star.
Hooke’s wave theory of light was an essential step forward in spectrum analysis.[9]
Hooke was the first to propose that the motions of astronomical bodies were a matter of dynamics. He published, Attempt to Prove the Motion of the Earth (1674), in which he offered a theory of planetary motion. employing the correct principle of inertia and a balance between an outward centrifugal force and an inward gravitational attraction to the Sun. He proffered three principles of gravity in a lecture entitled “System of the World,” given in 1674
- “ . .all Coelestial Bodies whatsoever have an attraction or gravitating power towards their own Centers, whereby they attract not only their own parts, and keep them flying from them . . . but they do also attract all the other Coelestial Bodies that are within the sphere of their activity”
- ”. . . all bodies whatsoever that are put into a direct and simple motion, will continue to move forward in a straight line, till they are by some other effectual powers deflected and bent into a Motion describing a Circle, Ellipses, or some other more compounded Curve Line. Hooke predeceased Issac Newton and this was later claimed by Newton. It is now referred to as Newton’s First Law of Motion.
- In that same lecture he also posited the strength of the attraction but wrongly suggested that gravity falls off inversely with distance from the object. He later corrected this in 1679, in a letter to Newton in which he suggested that this attraction would vary inversely as the square of the distance from the Sun. Hooke's theory was qualitatively correct. However he did not have the mathematical skills to provide exact and quantitative definition.[10] [11]Cite error: Closing
</ref>
missing for<ref>
tag
Modern Cosmology
A seminal project in the advancement of cosmology was COBE. With COBE, the extent and precision of the data gathered shifted the entire field of cosmology prompting the Nobel Foundation (Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences) to comment, "the COBE-project can also be regarded as the starting point for cosmology as a precision science: For the first time cosmological calculations (like those concerning the relationship between dark matter and ordinary, visible matter) could be compared with data from real measurements. This makes modern cosmology a true science (rather than a kind of philosophical speculation, like earlier cosmology)."[12]
Leading theoretical focus
The Big Bang
The Big Bang, a label bestowed derisively by its leading critic, Fred Hoyle in the early part of the 20th century, is basically a theory of the universe with a beginning, and possibly an end. Until the Big Bang, cosmology was established on an immutable, everlasting and unchanging universe, the Aristotelian model.
Until Georges Lemaître, the idea of a beginning was hotly rejected, even by those whose evidence best supported this theory, people such as Einstein and Hubble.
In essence the Big Bang is about a moment--an extremely short moment--wherein all the matter and energy of the universe is condensed into a space smaller than the subatomic components of an atom, and then are released in a sudden moment. The problem with this model of the cosmos is that prior to the moment of the Big Bang, it is not possible to actually investigate what happened, to scientifically research the nature of things, a problem that nearly lead Einstein to ultimately reject this theory.
Galaxies and clusters
Relic radiation
Cosmic strings
Inflation
References
- ↑ compare with cosmogony the study of or a theory of the creation and evolution of the universe. Sometimes creation myths are termed cosmogonies. Greek cosmos:order, the universe, the world + gonos: creation, birth. [1] Webster, M. Grand Valley State University, Allendale Michigan
- ↑ Munitz, Milton K. (1967) Cosmology. The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Paul Edwards (Ed.) Vol 2 New York: Macmillan
- ↑ A brief history of cosmology School of Mathematical and Computational Sciences University of St Andrews
- ↑ The Greek Worldview Center for History of Physics, American Institute of Physics
- ↑ The Michelson-Morley Experiment Fowler, M. Dept of Physics, University of Virginia
- ↑ Aristotle (384 - 322 B.C.) History of Astronomy, Astronomy, Cornell University
- ↑ Smoot, George, Davidson, Keay (1993). Wrinkles in time: The imprint of creation. London: Abacus Books
- ↑ Gribbin, J. (2002) Science: A history. London: Penguin
- ↑ When Issac Newton produced his theory of light and colur in 1672, Hooke took credit for it claiming that Newton had stolen his ideas about light in 1665. The year following Hooke’s death, Issac Newton published his work on light and colour, Opticks, in which he gave no credit to Hooke. Newton also removed all mention of Hooke from Principia
- ↑ Robert Hooke
- ↑ Hooke Wilkins, D.R. School of Math, Trinity College, Dublin
- ↑ The Nobel Prize in Physics 2006 Information for the public. p. 5. Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences Accessed 30.07.07